With the lid closed and with no clue how much time is on the timer, there is no way to know whether the cat is dead or alive inside the trunk. According to quantum mechanics, however, the question of the cat's state—alive or dead (mutually exclusive states, mind you)—is not a valid question, the situation is indeterminate until an observation is made. While the trunk remains closed and we remain outside speculating and placing bets, the cat is not alive. It is not dead. It is not both alive and dead. It is not neither alive nor dead. This four-fold indeterminacy is the case, is the fact of the matter according to quantum mechanics, up until such a time that an observation is made. Making an observation forces the state of the cat to resolve itself into one of the two mutually exclusive conditions. Then and only then is the cat found to be either alive or dead. As long as the box remains closed, however, the cat is literally not alive, not dead, not both, and not neither.
Thus quantum mechanics provides an actual answer to the age-old question: if a tree falls in a forest and there is no one there to witness it, does it make a sound? The answer from the perspective of QM? Your question is bogus. Until there is an observation there is no sound. But that is not because sound is only sound if someone hears it. Instead that is because, until an observation is made, the forest, the tree, the falling, and the physical properties of all of these (such as sounds) are all in an indeterminate state as long as there has been no observation. The fallen tree does not exist. It does not not-exist. It does not both exist and not-exist. It does not not-exist and does not not-not-exist.
I think that Schrödinger's cat makes a fine Zen kō'an.
Today I read these
fascinating kō’ans in Jin Y. Park’s book Buddhism and Postmodernity. The first one also involves the tragic fate of a cat [translation modified slightly for effect]:
Nanquan saw
monks of the Eastern and Western halls quarreling over a cat. He
held up the cat and said, “If you can give me an answer, one
genuine truth, you will save the cat. If not, I will kill it.” No
one answered. Without hesitating, Nanquan cut the cat in two.
In my mind, this
kō’an is fascinating for myriad reasons. But there's two in particular that caught my attention: (1) the violence to the cat and (2) the use of and impact of indirect discourse (assuming that the monks have just received an
extraordinary teaching). The two, of course, are intertwined.
Here’s my take on the kō'an:
1. By virtue of the force with which
they were employing words, it was clear that each side in the argument believed their
words were right and true. Further, since the words of the opposing
contingent of monks were spoken in opposition, each side was
asserting the additional belief in a dualistic truth and falsity that
these words were vehicles for. Yet when called to give a truly
correct or right word, they both failed. When the stakes were
minimal, they bought into the veracity of their own conceptions with
gusto and quarreled, creating a problem. When the stakes were high
(and only so as a consequence of the situation the monks themselves
created), their conceptions and verbalizations thereof were
completely impotent.
2. Each had mistaken the presence of
the cat as a source of suffering, as a source of angst, as the source
of a problem. In fact, each of the monks themselves were sources of
a faux misery blown out of proportion and treated as though “part
of the world.” They had been affecting distress with each other
over the cat. When the cat, a source of possible joy and a proper
object of compassion, is killed they are exposed to genuine misery,
to real distress. By inadvertently killing the cat and by seeing the
cat killed, the monks experience true distress.
Interestingly, a different source gives
an extended version whereby a monk named Zhaozhou returns to the
monastery shortly after the cat is killed. When he returns Nanquan
recounts the incident. When Nanquan gets to the part where he
himself gives the monks the ultimatum, where he says, “If you can
give me an answer, one genuine truth, you will save the cat...”
Zhaozhou immediately takes off one of his grass-made sandals and puts
it on top of his head and walks away. Nanquan sighs to himself,
“ah... if you’d been here you would have saved the cat.”
This seems to support my hypothesis.
In response to the teaching that was making use of indirect discourse
to convey its message Zhaozhou offers indirect discourse as a means
of providing a viable answer without falling into the trap set by
Nanquan:
3. The master, having asked for even
one genuinely true word or genuinely correct statement, had asked for
the impossible. Truth is not conveyed by language which necessarily
operates by virtue of treating as identical that which is clearly
singular. But even some sort of statement such as, “master,
genuine truth cannot be conveyed by words,” would not have saved
the cat. For that assertion too is so much language drawing on a
mammoth epistemological framework for its coherence and cogency.
What would’ve saved the cat would’ve been a response that, while
not invoking language, nevertheless carried with it the force of the
inadequacy of language to convey genuine truths. Zhaozhou’s
response was just such a response.
4. In thinking about this kō’an,
it strikes me that the
power of indirect discourse is in what it illuminates, highlights,
conveys, exposes, and ‘opens up’ by way of the choices and
exclusions that it makes and in the communicative forms that it
attempts and resists. A similar such ko’an is
one wherein a master replies to a question with a forceful yet
indirect answer [modified slightly for effect]:
A monk asks
Zhaozhou: “Ten thousand things return to one. To where does this
one thing return?”
Zhaozhou
replies: “When I stayed in Qinzhou, I washed my robes, which when
wet weighed seven pounds.”
The
monk in this case seems to be asking about ultimate reality. This
kind of metaphysical speculation is a snare. So the much more
enlightened Zhaozhou embarrasses the monk’s investment in this kind
of question by offering as an answer, as a legitimate answer and not
a redirect or distraction or irrationalist response, an account of an
everyday experience he had in a specific location at a specific time.
This strikes me as potent indirect discourse and an incredible
lesson in ethical praxis. What do you think? And what about the
poor cat?!?
No comments:
Post a Comment